Abstract
In relativistic space–time, Bohmian theories can be formulated by introducing a privileged foliation of space–time. The introduction of such a foliation—as extra absolute space–time structure—would seem to imply a clear violation of Lorentz invariance, and thus a conflict with fundamental relativity. Here, we consider the possibility that, instead of positing it as extra structure, the required foliation could be covariantly determined by the wave function. We argue that this allows for the formulation of Bohmian theories that seem to qualify as fundamentally Lorentz invariant. We conclude with some discussion of whether or not they might also qualify as fundamentally relativistic.
1. Introduction
Bohmian mechanics, also known as the de Broglie–Bohm pilot-wave theory, is a version of quantum mechanics in which the notions of observation, measurement and the macroscopic world play no fundamental role [1–4]. For the case of an N-particle universe of spinless non-relativistic particles, the theory posits a universal wave function obeying the usual Schrödinger wave equation
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/02d5432c-1f76-4e9f-ac08-6b7372251b20/rspa20130699m1x1.gif)
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/11ef4cb0-d284-4286-bc7a-4e40b4270fe1/rspa20130699m1x2.gif)
One common objection to Bohmian mechanics is that it is incompatible with, and cannot be made compatible with, relativity. Of course, the theory sketched above is a version of non-relativistic quantum mechanics, so one expects incompatibility with relativity. The point, though, is that the non-relativistic theory contains a certain feature (suggesting incompatibility with relativity) that persists even when, for example, equation (1.1) is replaced with a relativistic wave equation (such as the Dirac equation): the guidance formula (equation (1.2)) has, at any time, the velocity of each particle being defined in terms of the wave function and its spatial derivatives evaluated at the actual configuration point of the entire N-particle system at that time. The velocity of a given particle thus depends, in general, on the instantaneous positions of all the other particles.
Bohmian mechanics is, therefore, a non-local theory in the precise sense articulated especially by Bell. Indeed, the non-locality just described is precisely the manifestation, in this theory, of the sort of non-locality Bell proved must be present in any theory sharing the empirical predictions of ordinary quantum theory [5,6].
Unlike certain other ‘quantum theories without observers’ (for example, those for which outcome independence but not parameter independence is violated),1 however, the Bohmian type of non-locality has seemed particularly difficult to reconcile with fundamental relativity. Leaving aside the trivial case of a single particle, the usual guidance formula for Bohmian theories involving appropriately relativistic wave equations for Ψ requires something like a privileged Lorentz frame or family of simultaneity surfaces.
Many proponents of Bohmian ideas have thus become resigned to the notion that relativistic Bohmian theories will be relativistic only at the relatively superficial level of empirical predictions: the theories will make relativistically good predictions (including, for example, the correct kind of prediction for the Michelson–Morley experiment) but will involve something like a hidden, empirically undetectable, notion of absolute simultaneity. Such theories, it is usually conceded, are relativistic only in the sense that the Lorentz–Fitzgerald ether theory (considered here as an interpretation of classical electrodynamics) is relativistic—namely, they are not relativistic, not in a serious or fundamental sense.
The aim of this paper is to question this perspective by suggesting a rather general strategy for making Bohmian theories compatible with fundamental relativity. In Bohmian theories, the dynamics of the particles (or fields) is defined in terms of structures extracted from the wave function. The strategy proposed here involves extracting from the wave function also a foliation of space–time into space-like hypersurfaces, which is used to define a Bohmian dynamics in a manner similar to the way equal-time hyperplanes are used to define the usual Bohmian dynamics. We show how this extraction can itself be Lorentz invariant in an appropriate sense and argue that virtually any relativistic quantum theory, Bohmian or otherwise, will thus already contain a special space–time foliation, buried in the structure of the wave function. This makes it difficult to imagine how one could question the ‘seriously relativistic’ character of the Bohmian theories to be described, without simultaneously denying that any theory in which something similar to a universal wave function plays a fundamental role can be a candidate for serious compatibility with relativity.
Bohmian formulations that employ a foliation extracted from the wave function (which were considered before in [9,10]) reproduce the standard quantum predictions (as we will explain in §6). A variety of alternative approaches yield a covariant Bohmian dynamics but seem to disagree with the standard quantum predictions. Here is a brief overview. First, one can employ a foliation that may depend also on the actual configuration [9,11,12]. Second, rather than using a foliation, there also have been attempts to use only the relativistic light-cone structure instead [13,14]. Finally, there are approaches that do not make use of surfaces but instead introduce a ‘synchronization’ of particle trajectories [15–18]. For more details, see [19].
The argument is developed as follows in the subsequent sections of the paper. In §2, we briefly review the formulation of Bohmian theories in relativistic space–time, giving simple examples involving both particles and fields. Section 3 describes the construction of geometrical structures in space–time using the tools available from quantum field theories, while §4 discusses the meaning of serious or fundamental Lorentz invariance and articulates in particular what it would mean for a foliation to be extracted from the wave function in a relativistically covariant manner. Section 5 sketches a possible way to generalize one of the suggestions made in §3 which does not require a foliation, while §6 takes up the question of the relationship between the statistical predictions of the theories proposed here to those of ordinary relativistic quantum theories. Finally, in §7, we reflect on the question posed in the paper's title.
2. Bohmian theories in relativistic space–time
In the case of a single particle (N=1), the non-relativistic Bohmian theory sketched in the Introduction is a local theory: the configuration space is isomorphic to physical space, and the guidance formula, equation (1.2), can thus be understood as determining the particle's velocity (at each instant) in terms of the structure of the wave function around the location of the particle. In the more general case (N>1) however—and here assuming the general case of a non-factorizable, entangled wave function—the non-locality of the theory (necessary for its ability to correctly predict violations of Bell's inequality) becomes manifest: each particle's velocity is (at each instant) defined in terms of the structure of the wave function around the actual configuration point of the whole N-particle system. The motion of each particle therefore depends on the instantaneous positions of all the other (distant) particles. This non-locality is the root of the difficulty involved in reconciling Bohmian approaches to quantum theory with serious, fundamental Lorentz invariance.
To further explain the difficulty and to explain the general structure of Bohmian theories in the context of relativistic space–time, let us consider the generalization of (non-relativistic) Bohmian mechanics to relativistic particles and to quantum fields obeying a relativistic wave equation.
Let us start by outlining the general structure of a Bohmian formulation for N particles in Minkowski space–time M. A possible history of the particles arising from their motion corresponds to an N-path X=(X1,…,XN), where Xk=Xk(s) is the space–time trajectory of the kth-particle. The law of motion for the particles, which defines the dynamically allowed N-paths, is expressed in terms of a wave function Ψ and a foliation of space–time into space-like hypersurfaces (not necessarily hyperplanes).
The role of the foliation is to provide the notion of a configuration to be inserted in an evolution equation similar to (1.2). Such a configuration is given by the crossings by the space–time paths of the particles of any leaf Σ of the foliation. The evolution law can be formulated by demanding that the (unit) tangent vector
to the trajectory of the kth-particle at the point through which it crosses Σ be parallel to a vector
depending on the configuration on Σ, as well as on the wave function Ψ and possibly the foliation
. The law can then be written in the form
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/b980e1d3-088f-4f2b-84a0-2109e7d35ed7/rspa20130699m2x1.gif)
![Inline Formula](/cms/asset/88ccd5a1-cf59-4c7b-8a77-d3bfb9728eeb/rspa20130699im6.gif)
![Inline Formula](/cms/asset/b1c2a394-0010-40ee-9cdf-636c9450db6b/rspa20130699im7.gif)
As an example, we consider free (positive-energy) Dirac particles. It is convenient to use the multi-time wave function Ψ=Ψ(x1,…,xN), where the xk∈M are space–time points, and which take values in the N-particle spin space [10]. It satisfies the N Dirac equations2
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/e1b165e3-1675-424c-aa49-cfe9b5821d0f/rspa20130699m2x2.gif)
![Inline Formula](/cms/asset/cab19389-9c48-47e1-b439-dcda010c7c87/rspa20130699im9.gif)
The velocity fields that appear in dynamical equation (2.1) for the particles are
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/424e61c0-f2c6-4480-ad42-d3ded3a51a25/rspa20130699m2x3.gif)
![Inline Formula](/cms/asset/e10303e2-ea37-4e2a-b039-5bb167351faf/rspa20130699im11.gif)
![Inline Formula](/cms/asset/2bebc252-c0da-422f-9032-5462472905be/rspa20130699im12.gif)
![Inline Formula](/cms/asset/dc39eb11-319f-4dca-903e-f2e3936b4b04/rspa20130699im13.gif)
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/8d5480cf-4f00-4051-99a2-39b9d1e53eba/rspa20130699m2x4.gif)
Note that although we have written down a theory of free particles, their motions will still be coupled if the wave function is entangled. The theory thus includes precisely (but only) the sort of ‘interactions’ that make it so difficult to reconcile Bohmian mechanics with fundamental relativity.
In the special case of a single particle, the wave function satisfies the Dirac equation and the particle law reduces to
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/444b2a93-ae04-49b8-a643-f4d2ae28b1da/rspa20130699m2x5.gif)
There also exist Bohmian theories with an actual field configuration φ(x) on space–time instead of particle positions (at least for bosonic quantum fields [20]). As in the case of particles, the evolution equation of the field in a relativistic version should depend on the wave function Ψ and foliation [9,12]. It should be of the form
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/527ab4f7-1bb6-4630-aee5-87b2c85791a1/rspa20130699m2x6.gif)
![Inline Formula](/cms/asset/12083dba-00e0-4823-934d-edd06db601ba/rspa20130699im15.gif)
For example, for a real massless scalar field φ(x), we have
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/2b2858d8-52d1-46c1-b195-d63dc6f3afb9/rspa20130699m2x7.gif)
![Inline Formula](/cms/asset/036a0901-fe86-4633-b2f1-5882d1eb9e59/rspa20130699im16.gif)
The point of sketching the two examples above was to indicate the general structure of the Bohmian versions of relativistic quantum theories. In general, such theories will involve, in addition to the usual quantum mechanical wave function of the appropriate sort, two pieces of additional structure: the ‘local beables’ or ‘primitive ontology’ (which, in the above examples, were the actual configuration of N particles and the scalar field, respectively3) and a foliation of space–time.
It has been suggested that such a theory—involving such a privileged foliation of space–time—might nevertheless be considered a candidate for ‘serious’ compatibility with fundamental relativity if the foliation is not simply posited as a novel piece of absolute space–time structure, but is instead regarded as a dynamical object, itself obeying a Lorentz invariant law. Examples of such a law are ∂νnμ=0 [10] or ∂νnμ−∂μnν=0 [19], where n is the future-directed normal vector field to the foliation. (For the first example, it means that the leaves of the foliation are hyperplanes, for the second it means that the time-like distance from a point on a leaf to another leaf is constant along the leaf.) Such models, though, seem to have a strong un-relativistic flavour even if they are in some sense fundamentally Lorentz invariant. The Lorentz invariance seems, somehow, unserious.
A different idea, which can perhaps be taken more seriously as providing genuinely relativistic theories, is to extract the needed foliation of space–time from the wave function itself
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/a638619d-dce2-4fb9-8c7a-a871ea94876e/rspa20130699m2x8.gif)
![Inline Formula](/cms/asset/1bfd2e5e-2190-4e48-9b4e-f716248983b8/rspa20130699im18.gif)
3. Geometrical structures on space–time and quantum field theory
Given that the familiar representation of the wave function Ψ lives on configuration space (or a field space), it is not immediately clear how it can provide a geometrical structure on space–time itself, in particular the foliation . So the first question we must address is: How can one extract geometrical structures on space–time from the wave function? Here we develop the thought that, as soon as one considers quantum field theory, natural possibilities suggest themselves.
Conventional formulations of quantum field theory (QFT) are in terms of fields operators ϕ(x) transforming covariantly under the action of the Poincaré group
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/89c116ba-6ac8-432f-ae74-5a8ef29d9b76/rspa20130699m3x1.gif)
![Inline Formula](/cms/asset/f7896f48-7579-4746-888d-f19518e75cc6/rspa20130699im20.gif)
Thus, however abstract the wave function might be, the standard local Heisenberg field operators of QFT can be used to define structures in space–time. For example, with jμ(x), sμν(x) and tμν(x), respectively, the charge current, spin tensor and energy-momentum tensor operator, one can define the following tensorial objects for a wave function Ψ:
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/486d5517-d20d-4db3-b4d5-1790faf8912b/rspa20130699m3x2.gif)
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/709ba5bf-c9e4-413d-9069-bfea5c6db2bb/rspa20130699m3x3.gif)
![Inline Formula](/cms/asset/63baff40-e4e6-460b-9677-0937d794628c/rspa20130699im21.gif)
A QFT tensor that is a vector field, such as Jμ above, is already very close to what one needs to define a foliation of space–time, namely the foliation that is orthogonal to the vector field. Of course, to have a foliation of space–time into space-like hypersurfaces, the vector should be time-like—a property indeed possessed by Jμ in the case of Dirac QFT. However, the foliation will not be well defined unless the vector field is integrable [23]—a property not necessarily possessed by Jμ. One may take its integrable part [10], but this may then no longer be time-like. So some massaging may be necessary to extract a foliation in this way. We will not take up the needed massaging here. Instead we will explore, in §5, an alternative—and more general—way to formulate a Bohmian dynamics which employs instead of a foliation, merely a time-like vector field, which may not be integrable. In addition, in the next section, we will consider an unproblematic and simple way of defining a foliation in terms of the energy-momentum tensor Tμν.
Apart from geometrical structures of the type just considered, which are structures on space–time, we also have geometrical structures on the Cartesian product of N copies of space–time. Considering again the free Dirac QFT, an example is the tensor
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/66b44260-421b-41f9-a513-8ae490b36c99/rspa20130699m3x4.gif)
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/ba3a0f52-3da7-4956-be17-c14ced3479f6/rspa20130699m3x5.gif)
4. Lorentz invariance
The next question we want to address is that of the Lorentz invariance of a Bohmian theory constructed along the lines sketched above.
In general, a physical theory posits some dynamical objects and some law(s) governing their behaviour. For a given slate of posited objects, there will be a set of their kinematically possible histories. The law can then be understood as the subset
of histories which are dynamically allowed by the theory. The invariance of a theory under a certain symmetry group means that the set
is invariant under the action of the group. For example, for the theory of the classical massless Klein–Gordon field,
contains the smooth functions ϕ(x) on space–time and the subset
contains those functions that satisfy ∂μ∂μϕ=0.
A Bohmian theory generally includes in its ontology both a wave function Ψ and some objects—the local beables or the primitive ontology—which could, for example, correspond to particles or fields. The wave function Ψ satisfies an appropriate wave equation, while the local beables obey a guidance equation involving Ψ. We shall denote by X, a kinematically possible history of the local beables.
Under a group G of space–time transformations (such as the Lorentz or Poincaré groups), X will transform according to X′=ΛgX, where Λg is the natural action of an element g∈G on X. The wave function will transform according to an appropriate representation Ug of G: Ψ′=UgΨ. The invariance of the theory then means that
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/1717cf2a-5b74-46b7-a962-57ceb5769ce0/rspa20130699m4x1.gif)
Alternatively, writing for the set of possible histories X for a given Ψ, then the invariance of the theory under the group G means that
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/9559927d-422c-4b0f-b26c-0fa141c74227/rspa20130699m4x2.gif)
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/eaee5d2a-e06a-4e98-b18d-adc59e82fc61/rspa20130699m4x3.gif)
If the set is characterized in terms of geometrical structures on space–time, as we have seen above (for example, for one Dirac particle, the trajectories X are integral curves of the vector field
), i.e. if
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/57248e26-5697-437d-a491-459f05bc1bc8/rspa20130699m4x4.gif)
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/498a7778-25a9-4040-aa77-7fa0ec366945/rspa20130699m4x5.gif)
Examples of covariant geometrical structures are given by the tensors (3.2). Consider, for example, the vector field JΨ in the case of Dirac QFT. The natural action Λg on JΨ is
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/25344357-0555-4d67-a0ca-1725e6debd1b/rspa20130699m4x6.gif)
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/03a192c5-10d7-49e3-b76f-ea9480b1b53f/rspa20130699m4x7.gif)
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/50445a03-910e-481a-8bd3-872c9444d55b/rspa20130699um1.gif)
For our purposes, the most relevant geometrical structure is the foliation . Its covariance is expressed by the commutative diagram
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/3dd71a10-4746-454e-8b72-74492ed7328c/rspa20130699m4x8.gif)
![Inline Formula](/cms/asset/287f8636-5c2f-471f-892d-7c53435a599e/rspa20130699im31.gif)
![Inline Formula](/cms/asset/15175b2a-895c-4b4a-955a-643c8e8a678b/rspa20130699im32.gif)
![Inline Formula](/cms/asset/27f29373-99f3-4e08-93f0-f0b79c2eabb3/rspa20130699im33.gif)
As another example, which is applicable to any relativistic quantum field theory, consider the total 4-momentum
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/e5e85e6e-c5ae-4dc5-9d25-aa80bd4abffe/rspa20130699m4x9.gif)
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/ac921d91-5df1-479a-a6e2-ed463d4b7f8e/rspa20130699m4x10.gif)
Finally, considering the Bohmian guidance law for Dirac particles, we see that the velocity field given in (2.3) involves as geometrical structures only the multi-tensor J given in (3.4), which is covariant, and a foliation . For a covariant choice of foliation, such as the one determined by the vector field (4.9), the guidance law is covariant.
5. Generalization of the Bohmian particle dynamics
A main objection to theories such as Bohmian mechanics is that they must inevitably conflict with Lorentz invariance because of their strong non-locality. In this section, we point out that, even when it does not define a foliation, the most familiar kind of space–time structure in quantum field theory—a vector field on space–time—may afford a reconciliation deemed widely impossible. For this, it is entirely unnecessary that the exact quantum predictions emerge. It is enough that non-local effects arise in a completely covariant way.
We thus sketch here a possible relativistic generalization of the Bohmian dynamics that does not require a foliation, but merely a time-like vector field, and which reduces to the one with a foliation in the case where the vector field is integrable. We only discuss this generalization for the case of a particle ontology. It is unclear whether it can be extended to a field ontology.
With n a unit time-like vector field, the generalized law of motion reads, following (2.1):
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/05f90353-a862-4595-9b8d-7044a8285bd4/rspa20130699m5x1.gif)
![Inline Formula](/cms/asset/f4cd09fb-762f-493b-a383-1ad3c601acea/rspa20130699im35.gif)
![Inline Formula](/cms/asset/b22e4ca6-37cc-4ef2-bbc0-95d5104de7bc/rspa20130699im36.gif)
Σx is the surface that is swept out by the curves through x whose tangent vector at each point is normal to n at that point and which are otherwise as straight as possible, so that their tangent vector only changes in the direction of n. Explicitly, in Hamiltonian form, the curves that generate the surface Σx satisfy the equations
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/7c5186d7-6605-4b80-b879-9cf5ee662aac/rspa20130699m5x2.gif)
The surface Σx itself need not be normal to n. It also need not be space-like. Only when n is integrable must the surface Σx be normal to n and in that case Σx is just one of the leaves of the foliation determined by n. The Bohmian dynamics then reduces to the one given before in (2.1).
It is important to note that, unless n is integrable, the surfaces Σx do not form a foliation. Namely, while x∈Σy⇔y∈Σx, the surfaces Σx and Σy will generically be different. (This further implies that the relationship x∼y⇔x∈Σy, which is reflective and symmetric, fails to be transitive when n is not integrable, and hence is not an equivalence relation.)
While this dynamics is a generalization of our earlier one in terms of a foliation, there is one drawback compared with that formulation. Namely, the relationship between its predictions and those of standard quantum theory is difficult to discern. This is an issue we turn to in the next section.
6. Quantum equilibrium
Non-relativistic Bohmian mechanics as outlined in the Introduction reproduces the standard quantum predictions provided that the particle distribution for an ensemble of systems with the same wave function Ψ(x) is given by |Ψ(x)|2. This distribution is called the quantum equilibrium distribution. It satisfies the special property of equivariance: if the distribution is given by |Ψ(x,t0)|2 at a certain time t0, then the Bohmian dynamics implies that the distribution is given by |Ψ(x,t)|2 at all other times t.
In relativistic space–time, when the Bohmian dynamics is formulated using a foliation , there is again a distinguished distribution ρΨ (a generalized ‘|Ψ|2’ distribution) which plays the role of an equilibrium distribution and which is equivariant (i.e. has the same form as a functional of Ψ) along the leaves of the foliation. As this distribution corresponds to the usual quantum distribution, the theory reproduces the standard quantum predictions [10]. For example, in the case of the Bohm–Dirac theory, on any leaf Σ of
, ρΨ corresponds to the distribution on ΣN given by
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/817e8412-2ba4-4443-87a7-c96ae6c1afca/rspa20130699m6x1.gif)
However, it has been shown that quantum non-locality implies that quantum equilibrium cannot hold in every reference frame or with respect to every foliation [15]. That is, even though we may assume equilibrium along the leaves of the foliation that was used in formulating the Bohmian dynamics, the implied distribution along a space-like hypersurface Σ that is not a leaf of the foliation may depend not only on Ψ, but also—and in a complicated way—on the relationship between Σ and the foliation. It may therefore be different from the usual quantum distribution. Nevertheless, as discussed in detail in [10,15], this will not change the fact that the theory will reproduce the standard quantum predictions, assuming quantum equilibrium along the leaves of the foliation. (This is closely related to Bell's remark that ‘the laws of physics in any one reference frame account for all physical phenomena, including the observations of moving observers’ [25, p. 77].)
In the case of our generalized Bohmian dynamics of §5, unless n is integrable and determines a foliation, there is no distinguished distribution (or at least not an obvious one) that may play the role of an equivariant equilibrium distribution. (Recall that the surfaces Σx that are used to formulate this generalized dynamics do not determine a foliation). In particular, there seems to be no reason to have the usual quantum distribution along the leaves of any foliation. As such, it seems unlikely that its predictions agree with those of standard quantum theory. (This is also true for the models in [11–18] that were mentioned in the Introduction. These theories do not employ a distinguished foliation, and hence it is hard to even begin a statistical analysis. In theories such as proposed in [11,12], the foliation depends on the actual configuration and different initial configurations will generically determine different foliations. Hence, it is not clear how to compute the statistical predictions for ensembles of systems with the same initial wave function but different initial configurations of the local beables.) When n is integrable, however, the dynamics reduces to the one in terms of a foliation, and a distribution similar to (6.1) is equivariant along the leaves of that foliation. The theory then reproduces the standard quantum predictions.
7. Discussion
We have developed here the idea that the privileged space–time foliations (that have long been recognized as a crucial ingredient in Bohmian theories) might not need to be separately posited as additional space–time structure, but might instead be extracted from the objects already present in the theory—in particular, from the wave function Ψ. As explained in §4, there is a natural sense in which this extraction can be understood as respecting the appropriate space–time symmetries, so that a theory formulated in this way should be regarded as fundamentally Lorentz invariant.
Several distinct possibilities for extracting a foliation from the wave function (and one possibility for getting along without such a foliation) have been suggested. Further exploring these possibilities is a natural subject for future work. At present, rather than lobby for any one particular such possibility, we wish to merely stress that several quite workable options exist—indeed, as explained especially in §3, there would seem to be a plethora of rather obvious candidates as soon as one considers quantum field theories.
Everything in the type of theory proposed here—the dynamical law for Ψ, the rule for defining and the guidance equation(s) for the local beables—is fully Lorentz covariant and thus seemingly entirely compatible with the space–time structure being exclusively Minkowskian. Is such a theory then fundamentally—and/or seriously—relativistic?
This is not an easy question to answer, because it is not at all clear what, exactly, fundamental/serious compatibility with relativity does, or should, require. Lorentz invariance is clearly one necessary requirement. But it is easy to imagine that someone might dismiss—as clearly incompatible with relativity—the type of theory proposed here, simply on the grounds that it involves a dynamically privileged foliation. Frankly, it would be hard to disagree with this sentiment. But on the other hand, one of the important implications of our proposal is that foliations can be extracted from Ψ and will therefore in a sense be present in any kind of quantum theory, Bohmian or otherwise. So if the mere presence of a foliation renders a theory un-relativistic, it seems hopeless that a viable relativistic theory could ever be constructed.
Other at least semi-reasonable criteria can be imagined. For example, some might feel that good relativistic theories should respect relativistic local causality, or should posit exclusively local beables, or should exhibit some kind of relativity principle for sub-systems. Some of these have in fact been shown to be incompatible with experiment, and we are not, at present, prepared to take any strong position on their appropriateness, or that of other possible criteria. Thus, we are not in fact able to answer the question posed in this paper's title. We stress, however, that these criteria revolve around aspects of locality that are largely incompatible with quantum mechanics. Thus, if Bohmian mechanics indeed cannot be made relativistic it seems likely that quantum mechanics cannot either.
Acknowledgements
We thank Roderich Tumulka for helpful discussions. The opinions expressed in this publication are those of the authors and do not necessarily reflect the views of the John Templeton Foundation.
Funding statement
This work is supported in part by COST (MP1006). N.Z. is supported in part by INFN, and S.G. and W.S. are supported in part by the
Footnotes
3 Particle and field configurations do not exhaust the possibilities for primitive ontology in Bohmian theories. Other sorts of objects, like strings, may be considered in this role, and more complex theories may combine several of the elements already mentioned. It should also be emphasized that a Bohmian version of (what is usually called) a relativistic field theory need not use field configurations as the local beables. It is possible, for example, to consider a field theory with particle positions as the local beables [21,22].
4 The colons denote normal ordering (i.e. annihilation operators that appear in the plane wave expansion of the field operators are moved to the right and every reordering induces a change of sign, owing to the anti-commuting character of the Dirac fields). We further set aside possible issues that may arise in making these tensors well defined in the context of theories with interactions.
5 The commutative diagram must hold when ΓΨ is uniquely determined by . But if different ΓΨs, say
and
, both correspond to the same
, so that we may write
and regard them as equivalent, then instead of
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/7601cb49-05e7-4238-bc5b-9d5382552577/rspa20130699im46.gif)
![Display Formula](/cms/asset/10a5a245-00d0-47e8-8397-cf3d55263c66/rspa20130699im47.gif)